In Defense of Nonsense

New York Times Editorial. 30 July 1996


By LAWRENCE KRAUSS
Chairman of the physics department,
Case Western Reserve University,
the author of "The Physics of Star Trek.

LEVELAND, Ohio -- Four months ago, when his Presidential 
campaign still seemed viable, Patrick Buchanan appeared 
on a national television program and argued  in favor 
of creationism. This, by itself, is not so remarkable, 
given some of  Mr. Buchanan's other views.

What seemed more significant, however, was that the same 
national media that questioned  other Buchanan campaign planks
like trade protectionism and limits on immigration did not 
produce a  major article or editorial proclaiming the 
candidate's views on evolution to be simple nonsense.

Why is this the case? Could it be that the fallacies inherent 
in a strict creationist viewpoint are so self-evident that they 
were deemed not to deserve comment? I think not. Indeed, when a 
serious candidate for the highest office of the most powerful 
nation on earth holds such views you would think that this 
commentary would automatically become "newsworthy."

Rather, what seems to have taken hold is a growing hesitancy
among both journalists and scholars to state openly that some
viewpoints are not subject to debate: they are simply wrong. 
They might point out flaws, but journalists also feel great 
pressure to report on both sides of a "debate."

Part of the reason is that few journalists naturally feel 
comfortable enough on scientific matters to make pronouncements. 
But there is another good reason for such hesitancy.  In a truly
democratic society, one might argue, everything is open to debate.

Who has the authority to deem certain ideas incorrect or flawed?
Indeed, appeal to authority is as much an anathema to scientists 
as it is to many on the academic left who worry about the authority 
of the "scientific establishment."

What is so wonderful about scientific truth, however, is that the
authority which determines whether there can be debate or not does 
not reside in some fraternity of scientists;  nor is it divine.  
The authority rests with experiment.

It is perhaps the most immutable but most widely misunderstood 
property of modern science: a proposition can never be proved to be
absolutely true. There can always be some experiment lurking around 
the corner to require alteration of any model of reality.

What is unequivocal, however, is falseness. A theory whose predictions
fail the test of experiment is always wrong, period, end of story.
The earth isn't flat, because you can travel around it, period, end
of story.

This misunderstanding is at the heart of much scholarly debate in
recent months, including the  amusing hoax that a New York University
physicist, Alan Sokal, played at the expense of the editors of the 
journal Social Text. The postmodernist journal published a bogus
article that Professor Sokal had written as a satire of some social
science criticism of the nature of scientific knowledge.

It was aimed at those in the humanities who study the social context 
of science, but whom he argued could not discern empirically 
falsifiable models from meaningless nonsense.

The editors, on the other hand, argued that publication was based in
part on their notion that the community of scholars depends on the
goodwill of the participants -- namely they had assumed Professor 
Sokal
had something to say. They too have a point.

The great paranormal debunker and magician, the Amazing Randi, has
shown time and again that earnest researchers can be duped by those 
who would have been willing to answer "yes"  to the question 
"are you
lying?"  but who were never asked.

We must always be skeptical.  Being skeptical, however does not get 
in the way of the search for objective truths.  It merely assists in
the uncovering of falsehoods.

Another popular misunderstanding of the nature of truth and falsehood
in modern science involves the speculative ideas which often appear at
the frontiers of research. For example, the science writer John Horgan
has argued that such speculations are unrelated to the real world 
around us. But notions such as "superstrings" and "baby 
universes" are
not akin to arguments about the number of angels on the head of a pin,
much as they may bear a superficial resemblance.

They are merely the most recent straw men in a longstanding effort to
get at the truth. They would not be taken seriously by anyone were it
not for the belief that these notions, when properly understood, might
in principle one day lead to either direct or indirect predictions
which may be falsified by future experiments or else which may or may
not explain existing data. The debate among physicists about the 
viability of these ideas is simply a debate among those who think the
notions will be testable and those who suspect they won't.

No physicist I know has ever suggested that unprovable speculation 
will shine on its own merits, whether or not it can be taken literally,
or that it is progress to come up with a theory which cannot be proved
false.

Mr. Horgan is absolutely correct to suggest that this approach is 
impotent. But his error  is to confuse this process with what
physicists actually do, and thereby demean the notion of scientific
truth.

This whole issue might make for simply an amusing academic debate 
were it not for the potentially grave consequences for society at
large.

If  we are unwilling, unilaterally,  to brand scientific nonsense as
just that, regardless of whose sensibilities might be offended --
religious or otherwise -- then the whole notion of truth itself becomes
blurred.

The need to present both sides of an issue is only necessary when 
there are two sides. When empirically verifiable falsehoods become
instead subjects for debate, then nonsense associated with
international conspiracy theories, holocaust denials and popular
demagogues like Louis Farrakhan or Pat Robertson cannot effectively 
be rooted out.

When nonsense which can be empirically falsified is presented under 
a creationist guise as critical thinking, a controversy is created in
our schools where none should exist. When the empirically falsifiable
supposition  that someone was not present at a murder when his DNA is
found mixed with the blood of victims at the crime scene is not 
recognized as  nonsense, murderers can go home free.  Nonsense 
masquerading as truth has been with us as long as records can date.

But the increasingly  blatant nature of the nonsense uttered with 
impunity in public discourse is chilling.  Our democratic society is
imperiled as much by this as any other single threat,  regardless of
whether the origins of the nonsense are religious fanaticism, simple
ignorance or personal gain.

Perhaps the greatest single legacy our scientific heritage can bestow
on us is a well-defined procedure for exposing nonsense.

We would all be wise to heed the advice passed on by Arthur Hays 
Sulzberger, the publisher of The New York Times from 1935 to 1961:  
"I believe in an open mind, but not so open that your brains fall 
out."

Lawrence Krauss,
Chairman of the physics department,
Case Western Reserve University,
the author of "The Physics of Star Trek.


202.41.95.1 visited at 04:23:14 Friday, August 09, 1996
using Mozilla/2.0 (X11; I; SunOS 5.4 sun4m) from http://weber.u.washington.edu/~jwalsh/sokal/.